Previously in Immoral Mazes sequence: Moloch Hasn’t Won
Perfect Competition
In Meditations on Moloch, Scott points out that perfect competition destroys all value beyond the axis of competition.
Which, for any compactly defined axis of competition we know about, destroys all value.
This is mathematically true.
Yet value remains.
Thus competition is imperfect.
(Unjustified-at-least-for-now note: Competition is good and necessary. Robust imperfect competition, including evolution, creates all value. Citation/proof not provided due to scope concerns but can stop to expand upon this more if it seems important to do so. Hopefully this will become clear naturally over course of sequence and/or proof seems obvious once considered.)
Perfect competition hasn’t destroyed all value. Fully perfect competition is a useful toy model. But it isn’t an actual thing.
Some systems and markets get close. For now they remain the notably rare exceptions. Often people despair because they are intuitively modeling things as effectively perfect competition, at least over time.
This causes many people to think that everything must by default become terrible, likely right away, such as in the examples that open Meditations on Moloch, and Raymond’s kingdoms. And thus, that everything in general must become terrible.
The anticipation of perfect competition, rather than actual perfect competition, is often what causes things to become terrible. Anticipation of perfect competition creates perfect competition the same way that cooperation in a fixed-length iterated prisoner’s dilemma has a backward induction problem.
Fighting this instinct is important. Responding instinctively with the detailed explanation, that competition is imperfect is not sufficiently quick or emotionally resonant. Two quick intuition pumps for when someone thus despairs, or argues for despair, are that this argument proves too much, and that, again, when you look around, many things are insanely great.
Remind Me: What Exactly is Perfect Competition?
Perfect competition is defined as a market with large numbers of buyers and sellers, homogeneity of the product and marginal costs of production, free entry and exit of firms, perfect market knowledge, one market price, perfect mobility of goods and factors of production with zero transportation costs, and no restrictions on trade. This forces the price to become equal to the marginal cost of production.
If even one of the assumptions listed above breaks down, price will no longer necessarily be equal to marginal cost of production.
The linked-to definition calls it a ‘theoretical market structure’ for good reason – this is a useful way to model some things, but never actually holds fully true and is not actually a thing.
When I Googled for an example of perfect competition, this was the top result, the thing that came up in the box at the top:
Agricultural markets are examples of nearly perfect competition as well. Imagine shopping at your local farmers’ market: there are numerous farmers, selling the same fruits, vegetables and herbs. … Another example is the currency market. First of all, the goods that are involved in the currency market are homogeneous.
Here is how much perfect competition is a theoretical construct: Farmers’ markets were already, before noticing this on a later editing pass of the sequence, my first and most detailed example, in the next post, of highly imperfect competition.
Note that perfect competition is in important ways less competitive than imperfect competition, because there is no competition for differentiation, for iteration or improvement, or for long term concerns.
Super-Perfect Competition
We will define super-perfect competition as competition that mostly has most of the elements of perfect competition, but lacks free entry and free exit, which creates more production than there would be at equilibrium (and thus, also, a lower price). In particular we assume effective homogenization of products. The market coerces this production through some combination of trickery, force, mandates, exploitation of biases, false perceptions, cost of exit, rapid technological or regulatory change, predatory competition in pursuit of future market power, or other means.
Perfect competition destroys all the producer surplus.
More precisely, it sets their economic profits to zero and takes away all their freedom of action – capital invested in such production is risk-free in pure perfect competition so it earns the risk-free rate. Which in the real world right now is basically zero. In a closed economy of only perfectly competitive markets, there are no alternative investments to establish a positive risk-free rate, so as long as there is not a capital shortage across markets, the risk-free rate will be at most zero.
Super-perfect competition destroys more than all producer surplus. The saving grace of free ability to exit has been removed.
Producers in both cases also have no slack or freedom. They must follow exactly the ‘optimal’ short-term strategies. Anything else is sacrificed.
As a system approaches perfect competition, producer surplus is destroyed, producer slack is depleted, and freedom of action dies.
Perfect competition is at core a special case of perfect optimization, in this case of homogenized commodity production.
Again, perfect competition is an abstraction. It’s not a thing. But being very close to perfect competition in some places is totally a thing.
Super-perfect competition is totally a thing.
Perfect competition is where you can’t win. Super-perfect competition is where you can’t break even and can’t even quit the game.
On a scale where 0 is full monopoly with price discrimination and 1 is perfect competition, super-perfect competition is values greater than 1.
A clean example of super-perfect competition would be the market for rideshares on the internet. Another would be the airline industry, at least at some times in the past. The dollar auction works via super-perfect competition. Many of Scott’s other examples in Meditations on Moloch also involve similar situations, with players forced into participating.
In each case, super-perfect competition exists because market participants paid the cost of entry in anticipation of capturing a future market with levels of competition that would allow them to enjoy a producer surplus and make profits. When too many people make that same calculation, they become wrong.
Traditionally all of this is viewed as great for consumers, since they get the best possible price.
If all the consumers want is to cheaply consume a fungible commodity today, as optimized to simple metrics, they are in luck. Or at least they are in luck for now, since super-perfect competition often paves the way for future oligopoly. If they want anything else, this market won’t help them get there, because producers won’t give them anything else.
Thus, rideshares and the airline industry.
Universal Perfect Competition
The worst case for consumers is if they are also the producers – a world fully given over to perfect optimization of some defined outcome.
This is an incredibly strong and alien assumption to be making, and it has lots of strange consequences that are rightfully ignored in standard econ-101 models that are for thinking on the margin.
No matter how cheap prices of goods and quantities available might get, if you have zero surplus of any kind to spend on them, it doesn’t do you any good.
This is isomorphic to the standard Molochian future outlined in Meditations on Moloch. Standard Moloch-winning consequences follow.
Capital demands and gets the risk-free rate, which quickly settles at zero. Easiest way to see this is capital supply over time must be constant.
The Iron Law of Wages takes over. The only way to avoid it under perfect competition is a labor shortage. By assumption all consumption is by the producers, and capital generates zero return, so demand for labor is proportional to supply of labor, preventing any labor shortage. Thus we are in equilibrium right away. This drives labor’s wage down to bare subsistence. Any gains from superior production are wiped out by lower wages, and only benefit those spending down existing capital.
Any actions that are not optimal permanently deplete your stored capital, including non-forced consumption. You cannot invest in optional assets, such as slack or creating the next generation, because those willing to not do so are competing (perfectly!) with you for a job.
You get a Disneyland with no children.
One could even argue this has already begun – that people in many nations having less than the replacement level number of children represents competitive forces so strong that young people no longer have the surplus to be comfortable having enough kids. If labor is willing to accept wages below the costs of reproduction, the Iron Law breaks low and you soon have literal no children.
Worlds given fully over to perfect or super-perfect competition, by default, lose all value to those within them.
That last clause of ‘to those within them’ is important! They can have value to those outside that world, if they can get their hands on some of the stuff being produced. Creating almost-perfect or super-perfect competition within a compact space, ideally containing few if any humans or other moral agents, can be a great way to efficiently produce an important fungible good. Not every system of the world needs to have surplus and enjoy economic profits.
Over time, many systems that are not monopolies move in the direction of perfect competition, if nothing changes and no one does anything to stop this effect.
An increasingly static world, drawn towards its permanent equilibrium, would by default look increasingly like some combination of perfect competition, pure monopoly, and other inadequate equilibria.
This is a lot of where the ‘Moloch wins because essentially perfect competition’ intuitions originate. Take a system. In that system, assume that underlying conditions are permanently static, except for the participants. Assume the participants won’t meaningfully coordinate. Assume that participants who do better beat out those who do worse and expand and/or replicate and/or survive marginally better.
Extrapolate.
The fact that this hasn’t happened yet gets viewed as a ‘temporary respite’ from the inevitable triumph of awfulness.
And in the very long run, given sufficiently advanced technology, maybe that’s true. It depends. We don’t yet know the rules of that game. Details matter.
But even old Malthusian traps don’t work this way.
Things sometimes get bad. Once things get sufficiently bad that no one can deviate from short-term selfish actions or be a different type of person without being wiped out, things are no longer stable. People cheat on long term investments, including various combinations of things such as having and raising children, maintaining infrastructure and defending norms. The seed corn gets eaten. Eventually, usually when some random new threat inevitably emerges, the order collapses, and things start again. The rise and fall of civilizations.
The rise and fall of corporations or other organizations is often not so different.
Shocks are Inevitable
In the steady state, there needs to be enough surplus around to raise the next generation and deal with negative random shocks. And as per Scott’s second reason things might not get too bad, the horrible nightmare systems mostly aren’t actually efficient ways to get useful actions out of human beings. Neither is starving the people of resources too far. Things can only get so bad for so long.
If you make things sufficiently bad, before too long you get wiped out.
For now at least, poor folks still smile.
That’s not to say that this is a good solution. Our modern solution centers on robust competition and an industrial revolution. We let corporations and others drive each other into bankruptcy or dissolution. This can be because they get too far gone, or because outside improvements through technological and productivity growth create a superior alternative.
In the increasingly static and more technologically advanced future that is more of a true steady state and approaching its permanent equilibrium, both technologically and otherwise, shocks may cease to be inevitable and thus this danger would become much stronger. That’s a huge problem that needs more attention. It’s also beyond scope. It is important for us to remember that it is beyond scope and a different problem.
The practical danger to this system, that is on the rise now, is the temptation to not let this cycling happen. Preventing the cycle stops short term pain and protects the powerful. In the places things are getting worse or on pace to start getting worse, where Moloch is locally winning, this is a key mechanism.
This leads to another perspective on how people get to the ‘Moloch wins’ intuition.
Those that visibly follow Moloch here and now seem to prosper, here and for now, if no one is punishing them for it (and also, as per my not-yet-justified claim last time, Moloch’s Army is in effect rewarding them for these intuitions and punishing others for lacking them).
The things that exist and are big or visible, and thus seem important, are mostly steadily getting worse most of the time. Despite this, things overall kept getting better on almost all fronts for a long time, whether or not that is continuing recently.
But it’s tough to see that blossoming forest for the rotting individual trees.
That question again. How does Elua pull off all these unfortunate accidents?
One key reason is that Elua is antifragile. Accidents and disorder are good for business.
Next in sequence: Imperfect Competition
“it’s tough to see that blossoming forest for the rotting individual trees.”
I am reminded of how often I feel like things are getting worse, only to pause and consider what the world was like 50 or 100 years ago, and how incredibly much progress we actually have made. It’s interesting how easy it is to fall in to this trap of thinking things are going downhill, despite that long-term evidence.
Pingback: Imperfect Competition | Don't Worry About the Vase
Pingback: Does Big Business Hate Your Family? | Don't Worry About the Vase
Objection.
Perfect competition only sets the economic profit of the *marginal* firm to zero. If firms (and potential firms) are allowed to differ and enter and exit the market freely, the most efficient firms will have a producer surplus. In other words, the guy who can make 100 widgets a day makes a nice profit, the guy who can make 75 widgets a day does fine, the guy who can make 50 widgets a day barely gets by and wonders if he should go into the doohickey business, and the guy who can only make 25 widgets a day says “screw that” and makes doohickies instead of widgets.
I believe that is wrong. Certainly, when I speak of PC here, I am speaking of all firms.
But suppose there exists a firm with non-zero economic profits because its marginal cost is lower than the market price. Why not increase production? By assumption, this will drive some marginal firm out of producing, since it now makes (very slightly) negative economic profits if it allows the price to drop, so the price doesn’t drop until the marginal firms are all gone.
Or, alternatively, the model has nothing that keeps the less efficient firms in business. Your example of guys works because it doesn’t scale, they’re one person each. But that’s a very different model where firms are capacity-limited.
What you describe here, I think of as pretty highly imperfect competition.
Huh? Why would a company with non-zero economic profit (I.e. total income – total cost > 0) require that the marginal cost be less than the market price? If one’s average cost is less than one’s marginal cost at current level of production, and the current market price is equal to one’s current marginal cost, then one has no marginal incentive to change one’s production, yet one is profiting.( as (MarketPrice – AvgCost)*QuantitySold = TotalIncome – TotalCost = profit)
Is there some reason that one’s average cost would be expected to never be less than one’s marginal cost?
@drcota: Well, obviously, if MC >= Price you decrease production (equal is also decrease because it costs capital and because you’re driving the price down). So Price > MC even if you also enjoy what we can think of as negative fixed costs, or if you have fixed capacity, or something.
Agreed that you can make money because average costs are lower but that requires competition to be differentiated – there need to be barriers to entry or you’ll just get entry by enough competitors to change the dynamic, right?
I admit I didn’t actually think about this scenario when writing.
@TheZvi I was for some reason imagining that the quantity produced was a real number instead of a natural number, and I think that idealization is why I was thinking that keep production so that MC=price, rather than like, producing one fewer unit than that.
I think I was thinking about short term, before competitors would enter, and drive the profits down.
Wikipedia says that in the long run, there is zero economic profit beyond the normal profit.
I am somewhat confused about what the normal profit is. Wikipedia says it is equal to the opportunity cost of the venture. This appears to just say that in the long term equilibrium, each kind of business would make the same rate of return, but not that this has to be zero? But I could easily be misinterpreting things.
I guess that was what you were talking about with the risk free rate being only barely above 0 at the moment.
So, I guess the thing is that we would expect that, if the risk free rate is basically 0, then in the long run, if there is perfect competition, we would expect the profit to be basically 0, and therefore that AverageCost-Price would be basically 0.
Ok. Makes sense then, provided that the “normal profit” rate in the long run is simply the risk free rate, and that the risk free rate is basically 0, that under Perfect competition that the profit would be basically 0.
It seems a bit strange to me that the risk free rate would be basically 0, but, seeing as that is what we observe, well, I can’t really say that it isn’t happening.
[disclaimer that I don’t know what I’m talking about goes here]
(side note: I meant to post this response much sooner, but my touchpad bugged out when I was about to post it, and then class started, and then I forgot about it, whoops)
@drcota: Yeah, it’s all pretty weird. I never would have predicted such low rates as are happening now, but they’re definitely happening. I think you’ve basically got it.
I think Doug has the right of it.
If all producers are the same, then perfect competition implies zero profits; if profits were positive/negative, then firms would enter/leave and thereby push prices down/up at the same production level, thereby decreasing/increasing profits for everyone; this pushes the equilibrium profit level towards 0.
However, what if producers weren’t identical? They still make the same thing, but their supply curve is different; i.e. making the same amount of product is cheaper for some and more expensive for others. Well, at equilibrium, no current producer wants to leave or modify their production, and no others want to join either. This will happen when economic profits for the MARGINAL producer are zero, and when marginal profits from increasing production for everyone are zero. Note that this doesn’t require economic profits for non-marginal businesses to be zero; in fact, they wouldn’t be zero, because anyone better at the business than the marginal producer is doing better than the 0 profit said marginal producer is gaining. Note also that in this circumstance, better producers will often have ramped up their production compared to their marginal peers, until their marginal costs have gone up to match the market price. They still make profits, though – (because their marginal cost is below their average price).
Pingback: What is Life in an Immoral Maze? | Don't Worry About the Vase
Pingback: Stripping Away the Protections | Don't Worry About the Vase
Pingback: What is Success in an Immoral Maze? | Don't Worry About the Vase
Pingback: How to Identify an Immoral Maze | Don't Worry About the Vase
> increasingly static and more technologically advanced future
I question the assumption that these two things are likely to go together. Advanced computer systems are much less static in their performance than less advanced ones. Consider how cache misses, branch misprediction, and JIT performance cliffs can easily slow down basic operations by two orders of magnitude. I suspect that similar things happen in other technologies as well.
I actually agree with you here at least in the short to medium term. Technology does not in general lead to stasis on the current margin. In particular, technological *advance* is not static. But having a static level of technology is static, and there is some physical upper bound on potential tech levels. This is dealing with a potential future situation, in which tech has become static at some high level due to difficulty of further advance (physically impossible/difficult, or otherwise static situation, or what not). If that were the case, it lays out consequences.
To the extent The Great Stagnation is a thing, it is about a lack of technological progress and technology, not too much of it.
Pingback: Moloch Hasn’t Won | Don't Worry About the Vase
Pingback: The Road to Mazedom | Don't Worry About the Vase
Pingback: Mazes Sequence Summary | Don't Worry About the Vase
I don’t understand why you say that Super-Perfect Competition creates negative economic profit, at least in the long run.
(A) In the short run, absolutely – if you have an overfilled market and leaving isn’t free, the average person is going to be losing utility for being there. But that is only the short term! In the long term, I would expect that people would generally pay the price and exit rather than paying an ongoing cost forever, which would reduce the overcrowding, and move it towards an equilibrium of 0 economic profit.
(B) At least the above is the case for a market with demand. As you said in this post, shocks are inevitable – and that can create regular economic losses when a shock reduces the available space in the market but people can’t freely leave. If we assume rational actors, however, one would expect that the people in question would also hesitate to join the market unless the profits were good enough to cover the expected losses from having to bear the lean times or to pay the exit costs at that point. So the equilibrium state in good times would be “everyone in the market makes some profit, but not enough to entice new participants on the margin to join, given that exit isn’t free”. And in expectation, I would think that the profits would need to perfectly cancel out the losses.
(C) Of course, in practice, there might be enough irrational actors that the market tends towards negative economic profit over the long term. After all, in good times, they can join the market and experience gains in the short term, and while it may be a bad idea in expectation they might not think that far ahead or that information might not be freely available.
As another note, this covers cases where it is free to enter but costs something to exit. If it was instead free to exit but costly to enter, I would think that (A) and (C) would be inverted, though (B) would remain the same.
Anyways. I don’t know if there is something I’m missing, but I just don’t see how your conclusion about Super-Perfect Compettiion being “values greater than 1” would work in the long run.
Yes, in the long term of a perfectly static market inhabited by omniscient rational actors, you can’t get persistent negative economic profits. Break any one of the modifiers above, and you can – and they are *all* broken in the central cases we care about later in the sequence.
The relatively interesting question of ‘how long can super-perfect competition persist’ seems to have the answer ‘indefinitely long enough to be ended only by changing outside conditions’, usually due to mistakes/misinformation being systematic, which is the standard situation.
> Yes, in the long term of a perfectly static market inhabited by omniscient rational actors, you can’t get persistent negative economic profits.
Note point (B) in my previous comment – the market doesn’t need to be to be perfectly static for your logic to break down in the long term. The only actual assumption is omniscient rational actors, which is admittedly a strong ask.
I believe that you could make an argument that with the actors being homo sapiens instead of homo economicus, you can get persistently negative returns. But I ALSO believe the same argument could show that you can get persistently positive ones. Maybe people will misjudge and end up overcrowding a field, or maybe they will misjudge and leave it undercrowded; I don’t think you’ve shown anything suggesting that it would be the former and not the latter. This is especially true if we have a market with entry costs and not just exit costs.
Fair point on B, I acknowledge that perfectly static isn’t actually necessary. That’s an overreach. As you note, the omniscient rational actors is an extremely strong ask on its own.
The argument isn’t that positive returns *can’t* happen. They certainly can under some circumstances, and in fact I’m quite interested in this sequence in exploring how to make that happen.
I’m not making a claim that all fields or most fields are super-perfect – I’m describing a thing that can exist, and does in some places exist. It’s not universal. Later posts in the sequence describe situations where I claim this holds in practice, and I discuss that.